Using water to feed the fire

How NOT to heat up your blast furnace


Keith S. Taber


"From one of the known ingredients of steam being a highly inflammable body, and the other that essential part of the air which supports combustion, it was imagined that [steam] would have the effect of increasing the fire …"


Producing iron requires high temperatures: adding H2O does not help
(Image by zephylwer0 from Pixabay)

The challenge of chemical combination

School science teachers are likely aware of how chemistry poses some significant leaning challenges for learners. One of these is the nature of chemical compounds. That is, compounds of chemical elements.

It may seem obvious to learners that when we 'mix' two components with different properties we should get a mixture with a combination of the component properties. So far, so good. But of course, in chemical reactions we do not just mix different substances, but rather they chemically react. So, sodium will react with chlorine, which can be understood in terms of processes occurring at the nanoscopic scale where molecules of a gas interact with the metallic lattice of sodium cations and delocalised electrons.

Sodium and chlorine behaving badly

Although we can model this process, we cannot observe it directly, or even the starting structures at that scale. Understandably, students often struggle to relate the macroscopic and molecular:

As Sodium is a reactive meterial [sic] and chlorine is a acid. When Sodium is placed in Chlorine, Sodium react badly making a flame and maybe a noise. I think why this reaction happen is because as Sodium reactive metal meaning that it atomic configuration is unstable make the metal danger And as Chlorine is a dangerous acid. When sodium is placed in Chlorine, the sodium start dissolving in the acid due to all the particle rushing around quickly pushing together with Chlorine atom. Producing Sodium chloride.

Student setting out on Advanced level chemistry, quoted in Taber, 1996

So, for example, if we do burn sodium in chlorine we end up with sodium chloride which is a new substance that has its own properties – properties which are not simply some mixture of, or intermediate between, the properties of the substances we start with (the reactants).

Indeed, sodium is a dangerous material to handle: it will react vigorously with water (in a person's sweat for example!) and burns violently in air. Chlorine is so nasty that it has been used as a weapon of war (and since banned as an 'unacceptable' weapon, even in war). In the 'great' war ('great' only because of its scale) the way men died in agony from breathing chlorine was much reported, as well as the effects on those who survived the gas – being blinded for example.

"In all my dreams before my helpless sight,

He plunges at me, guttering, choking, drowning."

Wilfred Owen, Dulce et Decorum Est 1

Sweet and honourable? 1 (Image by Bruce Mewett from Pixabay)

Sodium chloride certainly has its associated hazards – if eaten in excess it is a risk factor for high blood pressure for example – but is certainly not dangerous in anything like the same sense. Many people put sodium chloride on their chips (often along with ethanoic acid solution). No one would want sodium on their food, or to eat in a canteen with a chlorine atmosphere!

When is something both present and not present?

Why this is especially challenging is that the chemistry teacher tells the students that although, at one level, the new substance does not contain its precursors – there is no sodium (substance) or chlorine (substance) in the substance sodium chloride – yet it is a compound of these elements and in some some sense the elements remain 'in' the compound.


Learning chemistry requires understanding how disciplinary concepts explained in terms of submicroscopic level models (After Figure 5, Taber, 2013)

This links to that key theoretical framework in chemistry where we can explain macroscopic (bench scale) phenomena in terms of models of matter at the submicroscopic (indeed nanoscopic or even subnanoscopic) scale. The sense in which sodium chloride 'contains' sodium and chlorine is that it is comprised of a lattice of sodium ions and chloride ions – species which include the specific types of nuclei (those of charge +11 and +17 respectively) that define those elements.

So, when we ask whether the elements are in some sense 'in' the compound we have to think in terms of these abstract models at a tiny scale – there is no sodium substance or chlorine substance present, but there is something that is inherently identified with these two elements. In a sense, but a very abstract sense, the elements are still present. Or, perhaps, better, something intrinsic to those elements is still present.

"We are working here with two complementary meanings for the idea of element, one at the (macroscopic) level of phenomena we can demonstrate to students (substances, and their reactions); the other deriving from a theoretical model in terms of conjectured submicroscopic entities ('quanticles'…).

However, there is also a sense in which an element is considered to be present, in a virtual or potential sense, within its compounds. This use is more common among French-speaking chemists, and in the English-speaking world we normally consider it quite inappropriate to suggest that sodium is somehow present in sodium chloride, or hydrogen in water. Yet, of course, chemical formulae (NaCl, H2O, etc) tell us that the compounds somehow 'contain' the elements."

Taber, 2012, p.19

Figure 1.9 from Taber, 2012

A source of alternative conceptions

This is easy to understand for someone very familiar with molecular level models – but is understandably difficult for novice learners. Thus we can reasonably understand why there are common alternative conceptions along the lines of students thinking that, for example, a compound of a dangerous element (say chlorine) must also be dangerous. Yet we 'mix' and react a soft, reactive, metal and a choking green gas – and get hard white crystals that safely dissolve in water to give a solution we can use in cooking, or to soak our feet, or to gargle with.

An historical precedent

Because science teachers and chemists are so used to thinking in models at the molecular level, we can forget just how unfamiliar this perspective is to the novice, and so the challenge of acquiring the scientific ways of thinking that have become 'second nature' through extensive application.

I was therefore fascinated to see an example of this same alternative conception, assuming a compound will show the properties of its constituent elements, reported by the scientist Sir John Herschel (astronomer, chemist, mathematician, philosopher…), not in a school science context, but rather an industrial context.

"The smelting of iron requires the application of the most violent heat that can be raised, and is commonly performed in tall furnaces, urged by great iron bellows driven by steam-engines. Instead of employing this power to force air into the furnace through the intervention of bellows, it was, on one occasion, attempted to employ the steam itself in, apparently, a much less circuitous manner; viz. by directing the current of steam in a violent blast, from the boiler at once into the fire. From one of the known ingredients of steam being a highly inflammable body, and the other that essential part of the air which supports combustion, it was imagined that this would have the effect of increasing the fire to tenfold fury, whereas it simply blew it out; a result which a slight consideration of the laws of chemical combination, and the state in which the ingredient elements exist in steam, would have enabled any one to predict without a trial."

Herschel, J. F. W. (1830/1851/2017), §37 2

So, here, instead of dropping marks on a test, this misunderstanding of the chemistry leads to a well-intentioned industrialist trying to generate heat in a blast furnace by adding water to the fire. But this does remind us just how counter-intuitive some of the things taught in science are. It might also be a useful anecdote to share with students to help them appreciate that that their errors are by no means unusual, or necessarily a reflection on their ability.

Perhaps this might even be a useful teaching example that could be built up into a historical anecdote which students might readily recall and that will help them remember that compounds have new properties that may be quite different from their constituent elements. So, while a mixture of the flammable gas hydrogen and oxygen can be explosive, a combination (that is, a chemical combination – a compound), of hydrogen and oxygen will not 'feed' a fire but dampen it down. Just as well, really, as otherwise emergency fire and rescue services would need to find an alternative to the widely available, inexpensive, recyclable, non-toxic, agent they widely use in fighting fires.


Compounds and mixtures are not interchangeable (Image by David Mark from Pixabay)

Work cited:

Notes:

1 Wilfred Owen was famous for his war poetry written about the horrors of the trench fighting in the 'first world war'. Owen was killed a week before the war ended. 'Dulce Et Decorum Est' referred to a Latin phrase or motto (dulce et decorum est pro patria mori) that Owen labelled as 'the old lie', that it was sweet and honourable to die in the service of one's country.


2 For some reason, "…it was imagined that this would have the effect of increasing the fire to tenfold fury, whereas it simply blew it out…" puts me in mind of

"the mighty ships tore across the empty wastes of space and finally dived screaming on to…Earth – where due to a terrible miscalculation of scale the entire battle fleet was accidentally swallowed by a small dog."

Douglas Adams, The Hitchhiker's Guide to the Galaxy

The states of (don't) matter?

Which state of matter is fire?


Keith S. Taber


A trick question?

Education in Chemistry recently posed the question


From Education in Chemistry

What state of matter is fire?


This referred to an article in a recent issue of the magazine (May 2022, and also available on line) which proposed the slightly more subtle question 'Is fire a solid, liquid, gas, plasma – or something else entirely?'

This was an interesting and fun article, and I wondered how other readers might have responded.

An invitation

No one had commented on the article on line, so I offered my own comment, reproduced below. Before reading this, I would strongly recommend visiting the web-page and reading the original article – and considering how you would respond. (Indeed, if you wish, you can offer your own response there as a comment on the article.)


Article from Education in Chemistry

A personal response – a trick question?

Ian Farrell (2022) asks: "Is fire a solid, liquid, gas, plasma – or something else entirely?" I suggest this is something of a trick question. It is 'something else', even if not 'something else entirely'.

It is perhaps not 'something else entirely' because fire involves mixtures of substances, and those substances may be describable in terms of the states of matter.

However, it is 'something else', because the classification into different states of matter strictly applies to pure samples of substances. It does not strictly apply to many mixtures: for example, honey, is mostly ('solid') sugar dissolved in ('liquid') water, but is itself neither a solid nor a liquid. Ditto jams, ketchup and so forth. Glass is in practical everyday terms a solid, obviously, but, actually, it flows and very old windows are thicker near their bottom edges. (Because glass does not have a regular molecular level structure, it does not have a definite point at which it freezes/melts.) Many plastics and waxes are not actually single substances (polymers often contain molecules of various chain lengths), so, again, do not have sharp melting points that give a clear solid-liquid boundary.

Fire, however, is not just outside the classification scheme as it involves a mixture (or even because it involves variations in mixture composition and temperature at different points in the flame), but because it is not something material, but a process.

Therefore, asking if fire is a solid, liquid, gas, or plasma could be considered an 'ontological category error' as processes are not the type of entities that the classification can be validly applied to.

You may wish to object that fire is only possible because there is material present. Yes, that is true. But, consider these questions:

  • Is photosynthesis a solid, liquid, gas, plasma…?
  • Is distillation a solid, liquid, gas, plasma…?
  • is the Haber process a solid, liquid, gas, plasma…?
  • is chromatography a solid, liquid, gas, plasma…?
  • Is fermentation a solid, liquid, gas, plasma… ?
  • Is melting a solid, liquid, gas, plasma…?

In each case the question does not make sense, as – although each involves substances, and these may individually, at least at particular points in the process, be classified by state of matter- these are processes and not samples of material.

Farrell hints at this in offering readers the clue "once the fuel or oxygen is exhausted, fire ceases to exist. But that isn't the case for solids, liquids or gases". Indeed, no, because a sample of material is not a process, and a process is not a sample of material.

I am sure I am only making a point that many readers of Education in Chemistry spotted immediately, but, unfortunately, I suspect many lay people (including probably some primary teachers charged with teaching science) would not have spotted this.

Appreciating the key distinction between material (often not able to be simply assigned to a state of matter) and individual substances (where pure samples under particular conditions can be understood in terms of solid / liquid / gas / plasma) is central to chemistry, but even the people who wrote the English National Curriculum for science seem confused on this – it incorrectly describes chocolate, butter and cream as substances.

Sometimes this becomes ridiculous – as when a BBC website to help children learn science asked them to classify a range of objects as solid, liquid or gas. Including a cat! So, Farrell's question may be a trick question, but when some educators would perfectly seriously ask learners the same question about a cat, it is well worth teachers of chemistry pausing to think why the question does not apply to fire.

Relating this to student learning difficulties

That was my response at Education in Chemistry, but I was also aware that it related to a wider issue about the nature of students' alternative conceptions.

Prof. Michelene Chi, a researcher at Arizona State University, has argued that a common factor in a wide range of student alternative conceptions relates to how they intuitively classify phenomena on 'ontological trees'.

"Ontological categories refer to the basic categories of realities or the kinds of existent in the world, such as concrete objects, events, and abstractions."

Chi, 2005, pp.163-164

We can think of all the things in the world as being classifiable on a series of branching trees. This is a very common idea in biology, where humans would appear in the animal kingdom, but more specifically among the Chordates, and more specifically still in the Mammalia class, and even more specifically still as Primates. Of course the animals branch could also be considered part of a living things tree. However, some children may think that animals and humans are inherently different types of living things – that they would be on different branches.

Some student alternative conceptions can certainly be understood in terms of getting typologies wrong. One example is how electron spin is often understood. For familiar objects, spin is a contingent property (the bicycle wheel may, or may not, be spinning – it depends…). Students commonly assume this applies to quanticles such as electrons, whereas electron spin is intrinsic – you cannot stop an electron 'spinning', as you could a cycle wheel, as spin is an inherent property of electrons. Just as you cannot take the charge away from an electron, nor can you remove its spin.


Two ways of classifying some electron properties (after Figures 8 and 9 in Taber, 2008). The top figure shows the scientific model; the bottom is a representation of a common student alternative conception.

Chi (2009) suggested three overarching (or overbranching?) distinct ontologial trees being entities, processes and mental states. These are fundamentally different types of category. The entities 'tree' encompasses a widely diverse range of things: furniture, cats, cathedrals, grains of salt, Rodin sculptures, iPads, tectonic plates, fossil shark teeth, Blue Peter badges, guitar picks, tooth picks, pick axes, large hadron colliders, galaxies, mitochondria….

Despite this diversity, all these entities are materials things, not be confused with, for example, a belief that burning is the release of phlogiston (a mental state) or the decolonisation of the curriculum (a process).

Chi suggested that often learners look to classify phenomena in science as types of material object, when they are actually processes. So, for example, children may consider heat is a substance that moves about, rather than consider heating as a process which leads to temperature changes. 1 Similarly 'electricity' may be seen as stuff, especailly when the term is undifferentiated by younger learners (being a blanket term relating to any electrical phenomenon). Chemical bonds are often thought of as material links, rather than processes that bind structures together. So, rather than covalent bonding being seen as an interaction between entities, it is seen as an entity (often as a 'shared pair of electrons').

Of course, science teachers (or at least the vast majority) do not make these errors. But any who do think that fire should be classifiable as one of the states of matter are making a similar, if less blatant, error of confusing matter and process. Chi's research suggests this is something we can easily tend to do, so it is not shameful – and Ian Farrell has done a useful service by highlighting this issue, and asking teachers to think about the matter…or rather, not the 'matter', but the process.


Work cited:

Note:

1 The idea that heat was a substance, known as caloric, was for a long time a respectable scientific idea.